To make a long story short, I think the lesson of Dorsey's problem of "intuitive bedrock" is that--whenever possible--philosophy needs to move beyond contested intuitions and find real bedrock: observational facts, establishable through common experience, that support one philosophical theory over another. Such bedrock may of course be very hard to find--but, as I think the above examples suggest, science can often point us in a more promising direction, if only we choose to pay attention to it. I've suggested before that analytic philosophy has often been too a prior-istic, and that the future of philosophy is natural philosophy: philosophy firmly enmeshed with the sciences. This, in brief, is why. Without science, all we have are intuitions--and intuitions just aren't good enough.--Marcus Arvan "Dorsey on intuitive bedrock and the philosophical enterprise" The Philosophers's Cocoon
Arvan responded to Dorsey's post about the same time I did (recall). On Dorsey's account (i) arguments are characteristic (or the tools) of analytical philosophy. The (ii) division of intellectual labor allows (iii) sets of systematic entailment relations are explored; and this generates (iv) philosophical progress, that, is we understand our theories. (v) Consensus is impossible because (v*) philosophy does not offer substantive grounds for the fundamental premises or posits in theories. As I noted, Dorsey's diagnosis of (v) is that there is an insolvable clash of intuitions. This generates a kind of spirit of tolerance in which philosophy is a kind of neutral tool to be used by people to navigate the world. So far my quick summary of Dorsey.
I offered two reasons to think that Dorsey's account is unsatisfactory: I noted, first, that the clash cannot be resolved is a consequence of a tacit democratic or individualist (moral) principle in Dorsey's account: each person's intuition is as good as another. Dorsey has not earned the right to this intuition given his own conception of philosophy. Second, because ends are eschewed on Dorsey's account of philosophy, such philosophy cannot justify its own practice in the way that the Athenian artisans Socrates around the marketplace cannot account for their practice. In addition, I also hinted that, third, that a focus on arguments i) may be too limited a way of understanding philosophy (leaving aside that there may be very different kinds of argument patterns).
As it happens, Arvan's response to Dorsey takes on these first two problems in Dorsey's account. First, Arvan addresses the inability to generate consensus by offering hope that substantive grounds for fundamental posits -- which he claims will be observational facts, establishable through common experience --,can be found by empirical science. The hope that this is possible follows from the example of the history of the sciences (he mentions astronomy and empirical psychology). In fact, Arvan relies on a Kuhnian picture of science, in which "mature" sciences are characterised by consensus over what counts as a phenomenon: "you don't get to assert something as a fact or observation unless it is widely--indeed, virtually universally--replicable." So, the idea is to find ways to put philosophy in position to become mature. Second, for Arvan the proper end of philosophy is truth. I discuss these in reverse order.
Arvan does not note that Dorsey had also allowed that truth is the proper end that each theory within philosophy aims at. Dorsey just doubts that this can be achieved with the tools we have. That is to say, Arvan is in no better position to justify his appeal to (another democratic principle) common experience than Dorsey was in order to justify his individualist (moral) principle. (We might say, that Arvan and Dorsey both represent different stands within a democratic ethos.) For, common experience ignores the deviant, the excessive, the rare, etc. (Arvan recognizes this because he speaks of an experience shared by 'virtually all.') In addition, and we know this from the philosophy of social science, the way the common is constituted by an empirical practice, finds it very difficult to maintain neutrality among competing values. Arvan's normal human subject is a construct in which various values are imported under the guise of science. Sure, this construct allows for means-end analysis in the same way deploying homo economicus does, but it can't tell you which values are worth having.
And this gets me to the main problem with such Kuhnian scientism (which aims at consensus) that has become characteristic of contemporary naturalism: in human affairs truth is not sufficient to vindicate a position. And that's because a theory may be true or sincere yet still be ideological or propaganda (recall this piece on Jason Stanley; and this piece on economics). For example, a theory can have a tacit status quo bias. So, you can study a normal human subject within given institutional (or cultural, political, etc.) constraints and arrive at a great deal of knowledge about it. But if you deny yourself the means to question these constraints, you may well contribute to maintaining an ideology. A sure way to do so, is, as standpoint epistemologists have taught us, to rule out evidence that fails to confirm to the normal or what is common. So, much as I love learning from science, if given the choice, I much prefer Dorsey's spirit of tolerance and collaboration over Arvan's purported progress.
Recent Comments