My frustration with this book is not that it lingers on what Machiavelli says to us, for here Levy is fully persuasive, but that it sets political theoretical debate in the narrowest of terms, between a liberal and a republican concept of liberty in which each is barely distinct from the other. The problem is not with reading Machiavelli out of context. (Against Skinner and even beyond Levy, I see anachronism itself as a totally legitimate intellectual practice.) The problem is with an approach to Machiavelli in which he is made to affirm our present way of life.--Robyn Marasco reviewing David N. Levy, Wily Elites and Spirited Peoples in Machiavelli's Republicanism, Lexington.
I enjoy reading reviews because they often make explicit what is submerged in journal articles and allow the attentive reader to reflect on her own practice. And sometimes they make me feel I am not alone on this planet.
So, one reason to be interested in the history of philosophy is to address something like this question: "How from some privileged (arbitrary?) starting point did 'we' get to here?' (Recall) With 'here' defined as either the the personal views of the historian or, more likely, the thought taken to be the cutting-edge as defined by folk at the top departments (when he was a PhD student). Answering the question is, contrary to what is common thought, not an excuse for celebratory Whig history (although it can certainly degenerate into that, too) because it can also unearth surprises (that is, we've been here before, sorta) or can explain why some important insights have been lost or overlooked, etc. (A nice recent (recall) example is Price's treatment of the fate of metaphysics.) That is to say, an interest in explaining the present status quo can lead to genuine (as opposed to celebratory) historical inquiry; this kind of inquiry treats works/thinkers/movements/ideas of the past as causes of the present (the effect). More subtly, it tends to entail that understanding of the present is thereby completed (it need not entail it because one may also (mistakenly) believe -- with a nod to the genetic fallacy -- that knowledge of the present does not require the causes by which it came about.)
There are others ways of engaging the past in which it is not so much a cause of the present but a means by which one can think critically about the present -- as Marasco suggests can be done with Machiavelli's writings --, that is, to prevent status quo bias. There may be other ways to combat status quo bias, of course, and, as we have already seen, turning to history may reinforce such bias. (As an aside, history for history's disinterested sake -- in which history is a quietist enterprise, also reinforces such a status quo bias. )
To explore history by which one can think critically about the present relies on a kind of limited symmetry principle in reading and engaging with the past. For, it requires understanding a past thinker first in her own (broadly construed) context to some degree* and then bring her insights & answers about that context to bear on contemporary issues, in part, perhaps by recasting our issues entirely. That is, it requires one to think that the present status quo has not fully assimilated all the insights available in the past and that we do not merely look back as superiors riding the wave of progress, but that thinkers of the past may have equal standing in addressing our situation.
As Marasco notes, one precondition for such a limited symmetry condition is to avoid using present debates as the means by which one accesses past thinkers. The reservation here is not the wrong-headed one that a past thinker cannot give us new answers to our questions (because they would not find these intelligible due to anachronism, etc.) It is a perfectly legitimate and sometimes insightful enterprise to deploy past thinkers in this fashion. Rather, past thinkers may help us understand more fully the limitations of our questions.
Continue reading "History of Philosophy as Anti-Status-Quo?" »
Recent Comments