Hobson claims that from the perspective of both liberalism ("laissez-faire democracy") and socialism a public, cost-benefit analysis of imperialism would find imperialism wanting. The mystery, then, is why it survives. And the mystery resolves once one realizes that imperialism benefits and greatly benefits concentrated, special or "sectional" interests. (He avoids the more Millian phrase, 'sinister' interest.)
Depending on one's training and disciplinary formation, it is incredibly difficult not to read the quoted passage and not think immediately of Mancur Olson's treatment of interest groups. And if I understand Paul Krugman's criticism of Adam Tooze correctly (see here), it's actually a good thing if that were to happen to you.
Or perhaps, if you are primed to see rent-seeking here, you think of Tullock and Krueger. The problem is that this literature is focused on tariffs, import licensing, and monopoly not imperialism (which tacitly is relegated to mere historical interest). That's not quite fair to Tullock, who is widely read and explicitly interested in vindicating "the classical economists;" and whose recurring mention of Gladstone in his short paper may well lead one to believe that the question of imperialism is lurking in the informal background of his treatment. After all, the implied lesson of Tullock's paper is that there are political costs from rent-seeking not well captured by a purely economic focus. And if this seems all too Straussian to you, Tullock has a known interest in Hobson (recall; see here 1963).
Hobson himself does not claim originality (his analysis is Smithian through and through) and evokes Tomas More. Some playing around with Google convinced me Hobson relies on a relatively late (1808) translation (Dibdin's revision of Raphe Robinson) of Utopia. But here I am not interested in tracing lineages. (That was the hook.)
As I have noted before (recall; and here) many people come to Hobson's Imperialism via Lenin and the tacit reception of Lenin in contemporary political economy and intellectual history. And once one has read Lenin, the crucial issue in Hobson's argument is Hobson's diagnosis of domestic underconsumption and over-saving as a driver of the export of capital. Imperialism then becomes a search for new markets (recall Duncan Bell's interpretation).
And from the Leninist-Marxist perspective domestic underconsumption is best understood as an effect of monopoly capitalism. There are, indeed, passages in Hobson that seem to evoke and anticipate this diagnosis. For example, in Chapter VI, Hobson writes,
It is not industrial progress that demands the opening up of new markets and areas of investment, but maldistribution of consuming power which prevents the absorption of commodities and capital within the country. The over-saving which is the economic root of Imperialism is found by analysis to consist of rents, monopoly profits, and other unearned or excessive elements of income, which, not being earned by labour of head or hand, have no legitimate raison d'être.
But as Hobson's wording suggests, his treatment is normative ("legitimate"). He does not think monopoly capitalism inevitable or necessary. In fact, as his analytic categories ('complete socialism' and 'laissez faire democracy') suggest he thinks alternative polities can be coherently thought. And that's because for Hobson imperialism is the effect of political decisions not the necessary outcome of economic laws. As he puts it (also in chapter VI), his economic analysis "dispels the delusion that expansion of foreign trade, and therefore of empire, is a necessity of national life." In so far as there are monopolies, these are themselves the effect of tariffs and political decisions.
Moreover, for Hobson, the search for new markets does not drive imperialism. (Simply put, he shows that the gains from new markets tend to be negligible. This does not deny some imperialist projects are pursued in the service of expanding markets.) For Hobson, while many interests benefit from imperialism, and sustain it, and while he recognizes all kinds of ideological commitments that promote it, imperialism is fundamentally a mechanism to protect high risk (and so high interest) investment income of creditors from political risk; as he puts it in Chapter VII:
That is to say, imperialism for Hobson is analytically connected with finance capital and its manipulation of the political process (and national public opinion).* If you pursue high risk, high reward investments, which effectively price in some defaults, you have no claim on socializing the downside risk.
On this view imperialism does not disappear with de-colonization, but is still exhibited in the gains from market turbulence -- "every oscillation of public credit short of this collapse, every risky enterprise in which public resources can be made the pledge of private speculations" -- and financial bailouts of the potential losses suffered by European and American creditors abroad.
I do not mean to deny that for Hobson protecting the political risks faced by a creditor class abroad isn't a peculiarly modern phenomenon. As he puts it:
To a larger extent every year Great Britain is becoming a nation living upon tribute from abroad, and the classes who enjoy this tribute have an ever-increasing incentive to employ the public policy, the public purse, and the public force to extend the field of their private investments, and to safeguard and improve their existing investments. This is, perhaps, the most important fact in modern politics, and the obscurity in which it is wrapped constitutes the gravest danger to our State.
And this gives rise to the modern phenomenon of competitive imperialism.+ But rather than treating such large saving surpluses as intrinsic to late stage capitalism, Hobson treats them as an effect of political decisions. For, Hobson does not subscribe to an economic destiny; he respects the primacy of what he calls "statecraft." And this means such saving surpluses are also correctable by political decisions. For as he puts it in Chapter VI:
Of course, diagnosing the desirably of an alternative political outcome is not the same as diagnosing the existence of a political coalition or a feasible pathway that can generate it.
*In particular, it corrupts national politics away from the path toward pacific internationalism toward acompetitive, zero-sum outcomes.
+He tends to deny the existence of competitive imperialism in the more distant past. This is an odd claim. Even the Romans (his favorite example) recognized other empires (especially the Parthian).
Comments