It is well known that despite their mutual admiration, and their common rejection of reformist/gradualist social democracy ('Bersteinism,') Lenin and Luxemburg also had some important disagreements. The quoted passage is from Luxemburg's response to Lenin's (1904) One Step Forward, Two Steps Back, and shows familiarity with Lenin's (1902) What is to be Done? In these works Lenin had advocated for an all powerful central party apparatus, as Luxemburg suggests. This apparatus was supposed to be secret (to avoid capture by the police) and constituted by an elite group of professional revolutionaries. (Lenin is also very critical of an exclusive, trade unionist focus on economic issues.) Lenin's argument appeals to the benefits of the division of labor among professional revolutionaries to the development of a professional cadre with different kind of specializations (agitators, propagandists, theoreticians, etc.) It is worth noting that the demand for secrecy is an effect of the Russian context (it being an autocratic police-state with few liberties of association), but the focus on professionalism seems less context sensitive for Lenin (nothing that follows hinges this, I hope).
Luxemburg's intervention on the side of the spontaneous activity is notable not just because she risks being seen to side here, in part, with those gradualists she ordinarily condemns, but also because it appears she rejects the advantages of the division of labor to the revolution. In particular, Lenin's vanguardism solves a kind of knowledge problem for the proletariat which, while being exploited, lacks access to the intellectual tools to plan and organize a revolution. (It's short on human capital one may say.) Because I am not a Marxist, I hope the next part of this sentence is not treated as thinly-disguised-polemic, but it strikes me that Lenin is right to think that his view is well grounded in Marxist-Leninist writings (despite their criticisms of the division of labor under capitalism).*
As an aside -- this may be more fairly construed as more polemical, but it is meant to be factual observation --, vanguardism does introduce an important tension into Marxism from a purely theoretical point of view. For, one of the key claims on behalf of Marxism, very clearly annunciated in the Communist Manifesto, is that it promises rule by the majority against the minority. And one need not be an Elite theorist to recognize how rare that it is. (The aristocratic element in liberal democracy -- elections to representative bodies -- secures (to be sure, legitimate) minority rule over a majority.) Vanguardism is a clear break with the idea of majority rule, which is why it is promised to be provisional. Of course, the non-trivial risk is that once in power the vanguard becomes a (new) species of elite rule.
So, Luxemburg's attack on the Leninist counterfactual ("The existence of such a guiding center would have probably increased the disorder of the local committees") is not merely an invention over a tactical debate, but also addresses a principled issue for Marxism. And here I want to call attention to two epistemic features of her position that are meant to respond to Lenin's solution to the knowledge problem for a revolutionary proletariat. First, she argues that central coordination does not increase unity and effectiveness, but is likely to cause disorder. And she attributes this to difference of positional or situated perspective which results inevitably in different stances (prudence vs enthusiasm), which itself undermines common agency. Of course, this is not a very convincing response to Lenin because the very enthusiasm of the masses is not sufficient to make a revolution (and often is directed at only local improvement without wider political regard). This is why Luxemburg's second point, the rejection of top-down policy, is significant.
Second, I read her as suggesting that many local struggles are each occasions of learning, trials that may in their very spontaneity and so novelty lead to new discoveries: where conflict induced necessity generates "great creative acts." Each local trial of strength between the proletariat and the authorities and/or capital provides a feedback mechanism from which to learn in which (the revolutionary consciousness of) the working class is trained. And, in particular, over time this will create a critical mass of "the existence of a large contingent of workers educated in the class struggle" (presumably capable of revolutionary politics). So, from her perspective the temptation of vanguardism is understandable, but with patience (and class struggle) avoidable.
By contrast, Lenin is quite clear that he thinks this is bunk--that a central clearinghouse is needed to integrate lessons learned and to provide the necessary expertise, to coordinate, and to educate. So, I am not suggesting Luxemburg wins this argument. In fact, with the benefit of hindsight we can see that he was right that vanguardism could achieve real power. But at the same time, Luxemburg was prescient in discerning that such vanguardism would inevitably lead to rule of a minority over a majority (as she notes "the self-discipline of the Social Democracy is not merely the replacement of the authority of bourgeois rulers with the authority of a socialist central committee.")
Now, what I want to note, in conclusion, is that Luxemburg's position on the spontaneous, bottom up education by the proletariat through local struggle is structurally analogous to (recall)the view that Michael Polanyi and then, more famously, Hayek develop in the 1930s on the way learning occurs in markets and the generation of spontaneous order. To be sure, knowledge about the spontaneous order generating features of markets pre-date Luxemburg, so I am not suggesting she influenced their development of the concept, which was already familiar. (And Polanyi is surely influenced by the way 'spontaneous' is used in chemistry and physics of the nineteenth century.) But anyone familiar with debates among Marxists at the start of the twentieth century, will be quickly struck by how important and intense the debate over revolutionary spontaneity is. This debate died circa 1920.
Hayek (1899 – 1992) and Michael Polanyi (1891 – 1976) came to maturity in the aftermath of this debate. While Polanyi never seems to have flirted with social democracy (and was not especially educated in economics), Hayek was clearly (and un-controversially) influenced by Wieser and charmed by Wieser's 'Fabian socialist' tendencies as a student. The Fabians were the standard-bearers of social democratic gradualism (which is at times compatible, of course, with left liberalism). So, it's worth exploring to what degree Wieser and the young Hayek were themselves enmeshed in, or at least aware of, the debates over the epistemic merits of spontaneous proletarian action.
*I am always a bit amused that Marxism requires bourgeois or upper class traitors for the revolution to succeed.
..."despite their mutual admiration"...
I wonder about this bit. I haven't read all of the items you're quoting from, but I have read Lenin's articles collected together in the volume _National Liberation, Socialism, and Imperialism_, and there...I do not get the impression of "admiration" from him towards Luxemburg. Rather, he (in his rather annoying way, one common to lots of Marxists, from the founder on down, alas) spends a lot of time calling Luxemburg confused, obviously wrong, guilty of selective quotation, of having put herself in ridiculous positions,of writing articles that are "a collection of errors in logic that could be used for schoolboy exercises" and so on. No where in that volume, at least, do I find any real indication of respect or admiration - just rhetorical street fighting. Similarly, in the papers collected as "The Russian Revolution and Leninism or Marxism" by Luxemberg doesn't seem to me to show much admiration for Lenin, but rather disdain and contempt.
(To my mind both are wrong, often obviously so, and Bernstein was mostly right, but leave that aside.)
So, I'm curious - do you really find "mutual admiration" in the earlier writings, which is, it seems, gone within a few years, or do you think that the name-calling, petty bickering, and rhetorical excess both engage in (though more so Lenin, it seems to me) is like a pro wresting show or something?
Posted by: Matt | 03/23/2022 at 02:04 PM
Hi Matt,
I am not an expert on the matter, but there are letters between them that suggest to me genuine mutual affection (mixed with mutual interest) and a practice of mutual socializing. See, for example, Letter of May 18, 1909 from Lenin to Luxemburg (which can be easily found online). So, it is my sense that they managed to engage in polemics with each other without it completely souring their interactions. But if I am wrong on this, it wouldn't change my view of this debate or even my judgment on their political characters, and I am happy to be corrected on this point.
Eric
Posted by: ERIC SCHLIESSER | 03/23/2022 at 02:14 PM
Yes, I'm hardly an expert either, and haven't read any of their correspondence, but at least by the time of the pieces I've read (noted above), the contempt seems real. It actually makes the Lenin stuff much less enjoyable to read to me - it's just so full of petty name-calling, while rhetorical excess, etc., often in the place of arguments. That's too bad, because the actual ideas are pretty interesting. (Annie Stilz has a really good paper she's working on on Lenin's theory of nationalism working some of these out, for example.) The Luxemburg I've read (mostly the one thing I've noted, and a bit of economic writing) is less rhetorical, but still seems full of contempt. (I'll add that this is something I hate about reading Marx, too - so much petty name-calling and point-scoring for no good reason! I guess some people like this stuff, but to me it's just awful.)
Posted by: Matt | 03/23/2022 at 10:45 PM