The second wave of liberalism (recall) has ended and liberalism may not survive. Some readers will say, good riddance, and to you I say, I hope you do better. This is the seventh post (recall here (I); here (II); here (III); here (IV); here (V); here (VI) in an open-ended series (see also here, here, here, here; and here). Critics of liberalism remind their readers during the pandemic that we care for more than "market logic" (Lisa Herzog in the New Statesman) or that there is more to the economy and living than "exchange value" and "how false our beliefs about markets are" (Simon Mair in The Conversation). Indeed, given the intellectual implosion of Richard Epstein this week, one may be forgiven into thinking that a variety of classical liberalism is truly on (ahh) a ventilator. But see these two fine essays by Nick Cowen. here and here; the second one reminds fans of the Non-Aggression Principle that "natural rights are conceived to protect life as well as liberty and property."
Friends and critics of markets have been much impressed (recall) by Hayek's argument that markets are impressive epistemic machines. But as is well known, Hayek thinks that the state and evolving common law provides the framework for the market and, at bottom, act as (to use David Schmidtz's phrasing) its impartial umpire. Hayek's friends, the ordoliberals (Ordos), went further (recall here) and claimed that quite a bit of state capacity, expertise, and even a proper ruling ethos is needed for the state to act as an umpire and to help the market function properly.
More than any other liberal thinker, but drawing on ideas visible in Adam Smith, Walter Lippmann recognized that for markets, the media, and public opinion to function, the state is needed not just as impartial rule-setter and arbiter, but as a generator and storehouse of reliable and usable information. Conveniently he uses the umpire analogy for this. As the quoted passage reveals, Lippmann didn't think that only the state could be a reliable source of information (the stock-market is a private association). It's compatible with his view that for-profit enterprise can also do so.
A core capacity of the modern state is to be a machinery of record. This is, of course, also recognized by those like Foucault and James C. Scott who argue that legibility of the population is a key feature of state-building and statecraft. This is a feature and not a bug of liberalism. Because (and to combine Lippmann and Hayek) in virtue of having a machinery of record, the market machinery can do its fallible work. That means that one of the distinctive mind-sets and dispositions of the liberal state is to gather data in order to discharge its proper functions. And, as Adam Smith already noted, to "prevent" the "spread" of a most loathsome "disease" deserves the "most serious attention of government" (WN 5.i.f.60.)
Of course, all states collect information. The distinctly liberal state does so in a rule-following fashion and respecting certain limitations which include the possibility of publicly reconstructing the data-chain and so being contestable.* One reason why modern (neural-networky) AI is causing so much trouble for liberal thinkers is that while it is rule governed its internal workings are also opaque and so difficult to contest.
We see this in the attitude of the German government which started building up the capacity to test early in the pandemic. Germany conducts "50,000 coronavirus tests a day." This is partly due, as the Financial Times reports, to its decentralized testing regime. (The US's reliance on the CDC makes it vulnerable to mismanagement, underfunding or simple errors of judgment.) But partly this is also due to the fact that German liberalism, as represented by the ORDOs, has not treated well-directed state capacity itself with suspicion.
No doubt even well functioning machinery of record can be abused or captured by sinister interests. But, going forward it would be useful for liberals to remember Lippmann's insight that maintaining the Weberian state as a machinery of record with the dispositions to act in the public's interest, remains a vital element of a liberalism worth having.
*Clearly the list is longer; questions of privacy, consent, and autonomy would also enter in.
Eric, I find your historical analysis of two long waves highly persuasive. If you look at the fin de siecle there was a major cultural reaction against the dominant liberalism of the Belle Epoque very reminiscent of what we have seen over the last couple of decades and all of those trends wend on to much fuller expression after 1919. I think that if you look at things from this very long historical perspective, what emerges is the constant problem that liberalism has with the question of a political order above and beyond that of the territorial state (national or otherwise). In the nineteenth century one emerged that rested upon a particular world monetary system, a world trade system, and a political order founded on the existence of several large and powerful empires (particularly the British but others as well). This international order was shattered by the War - a lot of the liberal thinking of the interwar period was about how to replace it (I think that is what Keynes's Economic Consequences is actually about). You can see the whole period since 1944 as an attempt to move to a particular vision of international order, particularly after 1989 when the major obstacle of the Soviet Union was removed. That order has clearly come to an end as well, it's cracking up visibly and has been for some time.
Posted by: Steve Davies | 04/02/2020 at 01:47 PM