Sociable Letters (by Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle) is described as “Primitive Letter Fiction Depicting Domestic Life,” under “Minor Fiction” in The New Cambridge Bibliography of English Literature, Volume 2; Volumes 1660-1800 edited by George Watson (Cambridge 1971), p. 976.
Last week, at a lovely conference hosted by Marcy Lascano and Andrew Janiak, I commented on a very fine paper by Sandrine Berges on Margaret Cavendish. My main, and perhaps only, qualification for the task is that Berges and I are co-editing a new translation of Sophie De Grouchy's Letters on Sympathy. (De Grouchy wrote a century-and-a-half later.) I enjoy such opportunities to expand my knowledge. Prior to preparing my comments, I was not entirely unfamiliar with Cavendish (1623-1673) because I taught her Blazing World, while being a PhD student at Chicago, ca 2001, in a survey course on 'early modern.' But Berges introduced me to many more of Cavendish's writings in political philosophy not the least of which is Sociable Letters.
As an aside, my early experience with teaching Blazing World was something of a fiasco. At the time I attributed the failure to the oddity and general implausibility of the work. But I now suspect that the failure was entirely due to my decision to simply 'slot' Cavendish into the syllabus somewhere between Hobbes and Berkeley without giving much thought to the fact that this also demanded a change in the way I framed the whole course. For, even if one doubts that Kant is the natural telos of early modern philosophy, most such surveys have a tacit, often unthought, notion of progress built into the narrative arc of the course. Cavendish does not fit such a dialectic.
Cavendish's works in metaphysics, epistemology, and natural philosophy are one of the central nodes of a collective effort among scholars of early modern philosophy to rediscover forgotten women of the early modern period. While a decade ago, among professional philosophers, familiarity with Cavendish's writings was restricted to a handful of expert scholars (led by indefatigable Sarah Hutton, Eileen O'Neill, Marcy Lascano, Susan James, Margareth Atherton, Karen Detlefsen, Lisa Shapiro, etc.) now all the 'young hip kids' seem up on Cavendish and articles and books are appearing in such rapid fashion that is hard to keep up. While language undoubtedly plays a role (Cavendish wrote in English), Cavendish's writings are full of funky metaphysics and so what once must have seemed like confused and false positions to those that chanced upon her works, now seem attractive starting points for philosophical exploration. In addition, because Cavendish is clearly engaging with recognizable and familiar positions in the history of philosophy, there is no obvious place to challenge her status as a philosopher.
Despite the fact that Cavendish was close to a number of political philosophers, most prominently Hobbes, her moral and political writings are not widely really recognized as political philosophy. This is, in part, a matter of genre; she presents much of her social thought in plays, stories, and letters. But given that genre is no barrier to recognizing Plato's Dialogues, Seneca's Letters, Plutarch's Lives, Montaigne's Essays, or Lucretius poem as a species of (political) philosophy, genre cannot be the whole or most fundamental issue. (This is not to deny that with the exception of Plato, all of the authors just mentioned are not automatically recognized as political philosophers by our professional peers.) While one cannot rule out rank sexism (see the judgment of the English scholars ca 1970 above), a historically and conceptually more interesting explanation is possible (or so I suggest in what follows). Consider Letter 150 (one of the longest of the Sociable Letters):
MY Thoughts, although not my Actions, have been so busily Imployed about Huswifry these three or four Dayes, as I could think of nothing else, for I hearing my Neighbours should say, my Waiting-Maids were Spoil'd with Idleness, having nothing to do, but to Dress, Curl, and Adorn themselves, and they Excusing themselves, laying the Blame upon me, that I did not set them to any Imployment, but whereas they were ready to Obey my Commands, I was so Slow in Commanding them, as I seldom took any Notice of them, or Spoke to them, and that the truth was, they oftener Heard of their Lady, than Heard, or Saw her themselves, I living so Studious a Life, as they did not See me above once a Week, nay, many times, not once in a Fortnight; wherefore, upon the Relation of these Complaints, I sent for the Governess of my House, and bid her give order to have Flax and Wheels Bought, for I, with my Maids, would sit and Spin. The Governess hearing me say so, Smiled, I ask'd her the Reason, she said, she Smil'd to think what Uneven Threads I would Spin, for, said she, though Nature hath made you a Spinster in Poetry, yet Education hath not made you a Spinster in Huswifry, and you will Spoil more Flax, than Get Cloth by your Spinning, as being an Art that requires Practice to Learn it; besides, said she, the Noise the Wheels make with Turning round, will be Offensive to your Hearing...Then I bid her leave me, to Consider of some other Work; and when I was by my self alone, I call'd into my Mind several Sorts of Wrought Works, most of which, though I had Will, yet I had no Skill to Work, for which I did Inwardly Complain of my Education, that my Mother did not Force me to Learn to Work with a Needle, though she found me alwayes Unapt thereto; at last I Pitch'd upon Making of Silk Flowers, for I did Remember, when I was a Girl, I saw my Sisters make Silk Flowers, and I had made some, although Ill-favour'dly; wherefore I sent for the Governess of my House again, and told her, that I would have her Buy several Coloured Silks, for I was Resolved to Imploy my Time in making Silk-Flowers; she told me, she would Obey my Commands, but, said she, Madam, neither You, nor any that Serves You, can do them so Well, as those who make it their Trade, neither can you make them so Cheap, as they will Sell them out of their Shops, wherefore you had better Buy those Toyes, if you Desire them, for it will be an Unprofitable Employment, to Wast Time, with a Double Expence of Mony. Then I told her I would Preserve, for it was Summer time, and the Fruit Fresh, and Ripe upon the Trees; she ask'd me for whom I would Preserve, for I seldom did Eat Sweet-meats my self, nor made Banquets for Strangers, unless I meant to Feed my Houshold Servants with them; besides, said she, you may keep half a score Servants with the Mony that is laid out in Sugar and Coals, which go to the Preserving only of a Few Sweet-meats, that are good for nothing, but to Breed Obstructions, and Rot the Teeth. All which when I heard, I conceived she spoke Reason;...[she said] my Maids would Complain more if they were kept to Work, than when they had liberty to Play; besides, said she, none can want Employment, as long as there are Books to be Read, and they will never Inrich your Fortunes by their Working, nor their Own, unless they made a Trade of Working, & then perchance they might get a poor Living, but not grow Rich by what they can do, whereas by Reading they will Inrich their Understandings, and Increase their Knowledges, and Quicken their Wit, all which may make their Life Happy, in being Content with any Fortune that not in their Power to Better, or in that, as to Manage a Plentiful Fortune Wisely, or to Indure a Low Fortune Patiently, and therefore they cannot Employ their Time better, than to Read, nor your Ladiship better than to Write, for any other Course of Life would be as Unpleasing, and Unnatural to you, as Writing is Delightful to you. Sociable Letters # 150,
It's easy to think that this scene of "Huswifry" merely exhibits (recall the New Cambridge Biography) "domestic life" of a very wealthy landlord. But is worth noting, first, that the "Governess" in charge of the estate is explicitly recognized as speaking "reason." This is a firm commitment to the rationality of women's thought. Second, the approved argument defends the division of labor, and offers an argument from efficiency of specialization: the idle, unskilled household labor cannot compete in quality and price with the shopkeepers and the laborers they buy from. Third, the argument defends the "liberty" of the servants in order to both play as well as develop their intellectual faculties--this is a firm commitment to Enlightenment of the non-elite. It is notable, too, that their readings are not said to be Scriptures, but (rather?) works that help cultivate their "Understandings, and Increase their Knowledges, and Quicken their Wit." The subsequent happiness of the servants is a valuable end in itself. Fourth, in addition, the argument appeals to prudence: happy servants are likely to be more loyal (and docile)--I'll offer more explicit evidence of this below. (These four features all anticipate Adam Smith.)
Even so, one may resist my claim that this is an instance of political philosophy because an objector may claim that household-management is 'private.' If Cavendish were a (proto-)Liberal, then this objection would hold. But nobody thinks that. Her writings exhibit a fondness for social and (it must be admitted) racialized hierarchies. So, she is not a Liberal. So, all one needs to show is that she thinks that the management of a kingdom can be compared to estate-management. For if she does think that these are strictly analogous, then in the passage just quoted, she is also offering rational advice not just on the art of political rule, but on some of the key features of sound political organization. Consider, thus, this earlier passage from Sociable Letters:
A Good Master is to know How to Command, When to Command, and What to Command; also When to Bestow, What to Bestow, & How much to Bestow on a Good Servant; also to fit Servants to Imployments, and Imployments to Servants; also to know How and When to Restrain them, and when to give them Liberty; also to observe, which of his Servants be fit to be Ruled with Austerity or Severity, and which with Clemency, and to Reward and Punish them Properly, Timely and Justly; Likewise when to make them Work, and when to let them Play or Sport; as also when to Keep them at a Distance, and when to Associate Himself with them; And truly, I should sooner chuse to Associate my Self with the Company of my Servants, had they good Breeding, or were Capable to Learn and Imitate what did belong to good Behaviour, than with Strangers, for Good Servants are Friends as well as Servants, nay, Servants are a Guard to their Masters, for Good & Faithfull Servants will Dye for the Safeguard of their Masters Life, and they will indure any Torments rather than Betray their Masters; and it is the Duty of Servants so to Do, for Servants ow almost as much Duty to their Masters, as Children to their Parents, or Subjects to their Natural Prince, for Servants are not on∣ly Govern'd, but Instructed, Fed, and Main∣tain'd; and what greater Crime is there, than to be a Traitor to their Governour, Tutor, and Nourisher of their Life? And every Master, the Meanest that is, is a Father and a King in his own Family--Sociable Letters, 61.
Now, the idea that estate-management is a template for political management does not originate with Cavendish. The idea is familiar from Aristotle's Politics 1, where household management is thought intrinsic to the needs of the polity. But Cavendish's treatment is more in the spirit of Xenophon. For, Xenophon's writings leave much more space for sharing in the responsibility by males and females of running an estate (see his treatment at the end of chapter 3 of Oeconomicus).* In addition, a key thought in Xenophon's Cyropaedia is that happy soldiers make loyal and willing soldiers. So, Cavendish is artfully developing these thoughts in a modern context.
Of course, Xenophon is generally only read by philosophers in order to find other evidence on Socrates's life and is most certainly not treated as a political philosopher (for evidence, see the entry on Ancient political philosophy at the venerable Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, where he is omitted). One need not admire Cavendish's or Xenophon's politics, to learn to recognize that a political philosophy without room for reflection on the art and nature of ruling is incomplete.
Recent Comments